Quintisection of an Angle
One of the most famous geometrical constructions in Euclid's
"Elements" is to divide a line segment in "extreme and mean
ratio" (Book VI, Prop 30) or, equivalently, to divide a line
segment into two parts a,b such that a rectangle with sides
a+b and b has the same area as a square of size a^2 (Book II,
Prop 11). Such a figure is often called a "golden rectangle.
Obviously by equating (a+b)b to a^2 we have the equation
ab + b^2 = a^2, and if we divide both sides by b^2 this gives
x + 1 = x^2 where x = a/b. The roots of this equation are
r = (1+SQR(5))/2 and r' = (1-SQR(5))/2. One of the many
interesting properties of r is that it is the ratio of a
diagonal to a side of a regular pentgon. Thus it allows us
to construct a regular pentagon and quintisect a circle.
We can also construct a right triangle with hypotenuse 1 and
sides of length (1/r) and SQR(1/r). Letting "beta" denote the
angle opposite the leg of length (1/r) we have sin(beta)=1/r.
We might wonder if the angle beta can be quintisected by
elementary Euclidean methods (ruler and compass). To prove
that it can't, observe that if sin(beta) = 1/r then we have
tan(beta) = SQR(1/r), which is constructible. Now we can
express tan(beta/5) in terms of tan(beta) by making use
of the trigonometric relation
tan(x) + tan(y)
tan(x+y) = ----------------
1 - tan(x)tan(y)
Letting T denote tan(beta/5), we have the identity
5 - 10T^2 + T^4
tan(beta) = T -----------------
1 - 10T^2 + 5T^4
We've defined tan(beta) as the quantity SQR((sqrt(5)-1)/2), so
if we square both sides of the above equation, multiply by 2,
add 1, and square again, and make the substitution x = T^2,
we arrive at
x^10 - 15x^9 - 605x^8 + 5260x^7 - 15070x^6 + 23126x^5
- 16370x^4 + 4460x^3 - 595x^2 + 65x - 1 = 0
Now we only need to prove that this polynomial neither factors nor
decomposes into quadratics. In other words, from elementary Galois
theory
If the magnitude w is constructible by Euclidean methods, then
the degree of its minimum polynomial with rational coefficients
is a power of 2.
Thus, if the minimal polynomial with root w is NOT a power of 2,
it follows that w is not constructible by Euclidean means. (Note
that the converse of this theorem is not true, because it's
actually possible to have a magnitude w whose minimal polynomial
is of degree 2^n but which cannot be constructed.)
If beta/5 could be constructed, then tan(beta/5)^2 could also be
constructed, and this magnitude is a root of the 10th degree
polynomial given above. To prove that it is the minimum polynomial
for that magnitude, make the substitution x = y + 2, which gives
y^10 + 5y^9 - 695y^8 - 5620y^7 - 15910y^6 - 9090y^5
+ 58850y^4 + 183500y^3 + 259525y^2 + 191525y + 58805 = 0
By Eisenstein's criterion this is irreducible, so the minimum
polynomial over the rationals with root tan(beta/5)^2 has degree
10, which is not a power of 2. Therefore, beta/5 cannot be
constructed by Euclidean methods.
This is exactly similar to the method of proving that an arbitrary
angle cannot be trisected by Euclidean means. The ancient Greeks
sought a way of trisecting any angle, but since pi/3 is constructible
this would imply that we could construct the magnitude w = 2cos(pi/9),
which is a root of p(x) = x^3 - 3x - 1. We know this is the minimum
polynomial because if we make the substitution x = y + 1 we have
p(y) = y^3 + 3y^2 - 3, which is irreducible by Eisenstein's criterion.
Thus the degree of the minimum field extension of 2cos(pi/9) over the
rationals is of degree 3, which is not a power of 2, so it cannot be
constructed by Euclidean methods.
Notice that in both examples we had to perform a substitution of
variables into the polynomial to bring a it into a form where
Eisenstein's criterion applies. I don't know of any systematic
way of finding the right substitution, other than trial and error.
This raises an interesting question: If a polynomial p(x) is
irreducible over the rationals, does there necessarily exist a
bi-linear change of variables, i.e., x -> (ay+b)/(cy+d) such
that the resulting polynomial in y satisfies the conditions of
Eisenstein's criterion? Also, assuming p(x) is irreducible,
how many substitutions would we expect to try (in some natural
order) before finding one that works? Also, what is the analog
of Eisenstein's criterion for testing primality of integers?
Return to MathPages Main Menu
Сайт управляется системой
uCoz