A Mirror to Physics
"Although to penetrate into the intimate mysteries of
nature and thence to learn the true causes of phenomena
is not allowed to us, nevertheless it can happen that
a certain fictive hypothesis may suffice for explaining
many phenomena."
Leonhard Euler, 1748
Question: "What does that sign say?"
Answer: "It doesn't say anything, you have to read it."
Traditional
One of the most frequently asked questions in sci.physics is
why the image of an object appears reversed left-to-right rather
than top-to-bottom when viewed in a mirror. By implication, the
"reversal" in question is relative to how the object appears when
viewed directly. The answer, as explained by every introductory
text on optics, is simply that an image viewed through a mirror
appears reversed about the axis around which the viewer rotated
his field of sight in turning from the direct to the reflected
image. Since we ordinarily rotate our field of sight about a
vertical axis, mirror images usually appear reversed left-to-right.
(For a fuller explanation, see What Mirrors Do.)
Sometimes, however, we come across a completely different
"explanation" of "what mirrors do", the idea being that mirrors
actually reverse things "front-to-back", as illustrated by a
drawing like this:
mirror reflected
chair | chair
|
/| | |\
|| | ||
||____ | ____||
|____/| | |\____|
|| | | | || ||
| | | | |
|
The most interesting thing about this "explanation" is that it's
clearly based on a counter-factual premise. The "chair" shown on
the right side of this drawing does not exist. What really exists
are reflected rays of light bearing a particular relationship to
the direct rays of light from the chair. The corresponding images,
which are 2D projections of those families of light rays for a
particular observer, appear reversed about the axis of the observer's
rotation. Nevertheless, the counter-factual explanation based on
the fictive hypothesis of an imaginary chair with imaginary 3D
properties appeals strongly to many people. It's actually given
as "the answer" in the sci.physics FAQ written by Scott Chase based
on an "explanation" given in one of Isaac Asimov's books.
This is a nice example of a "fictive hypothesis" that is quite
successful at explaining things - up to a point. If we are
standing next to the real chair we can deduce how the reflected
image will appear from various points of view by *imagining*
another chair in the fictitious "space" on the other side of the
mirror, with the understanding that all "objects" in that "space"
are reversed front-to-back, i.e. symmetrical with the real objects
about the plane surface of the mirror. Of course, there's a point
at which this fictive hypothesis ceases to be useful. For example,
if we try to walk over to the reflected chair and sit down we
quickly discover the limitations of conceptualizing reflected
images as 3D objects.
The reason this counter-factual description seems so natural is that
we are accustomed to dealing with our psychological constructions
rather than with the primary sense perceptions on which those
constructions are based. We normally presume a fairly reliable
isomorphism between our perceptions and the associated mental
constructs, but mirrors are somewhat unusual in that they present
us with sense perceptions that we intentionally construe in a
counter-factual way. A mirror is *designed* to simulate the sense
impressions of things that really aren't "there". Notice that
mirrors are among the few objects on which we almost never focus
our eyes. We don't look AT mirrors, we look IN mirrors, with our
focal lengths adjusted into the fictitious space on the "other
side".
In addition to the natural tendancy to deal with our mental
constructs rather than our direct perceptions, the counter-factual
explanation of what mirrors "do" is motivated partly by the
traditional desire of physicists to separate the observer from
the phenomenon. The original question asks what mirrors "do", and
we tend to think this should be definable without reference to
what the observer does (e.g., rotating his field of sight).
However, a question about the *appearance of images* can only
be properly answered by considering not only what mirrors "do",
but also what WE do when we look in mirrors. If we remove the
observer from consideration, we can no longer deal with images
and appearances (which is what the question asks about), because
an image implies a point of view and an orientation. Without
these concepts we can't really address the question at all. For
example, the Scott Chase FAQ article declines to even acknowledge
the basic observation that prompts the question (reflected text
appearing backwards but not upside-down), and never addresses the
correlation between the observer's axis of rotation and the
resulting appearance of the reflected image.
Overall, mirrors provide an interesting reflection of physics in
general and the sci.physics newsgroup in particular. They nicely
illustrate two problematical features of our thought processes:
(1) the tension between our imaginary psychological models and our
direct perceptions, and (2) our tendancy to separate the observer
from the phenomenon.
For a related discussion, see Reflections on the Mirror Question.
Return to MathPages Main Menu
Сайт управляется системой
uCoz